Logical fallacy
The neutrality of this article is disputed. |
A logical fallacy is an error in logical argument which is independent of the truth of the premises. It is a flaw in the structure of an argument as opposed to an error in its premises. When there is a fallacy in an argument it is said to be invalid. The presence of a logical fallacy in an argument does not necessarily imply anything about the argument's premises or its conclusion. Both may actually be true, but the argument is still invalid because the conclusion does not follow from the premises using the inference principles of the argument. By extension, an argument can have a logical fallacy even if the argument is not a purely logical one; for instance an argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality can be said to have a logical fallacy.
Recognizing fallacies in practical arguments may be difficult since arguments are often structured using rhetorical patterns that obscure the logical connections between assertions. As we illustrate with various examples, fallacies may also exploit the emotions or intellectual or psychological weaknesses of the interlocutor. Having the capability of recognizing logical fallacies in arguments will hopefully reduce the likelihood of such an occurrence.
A different approach to understanding and classifying fallacies is provided by argumentation theory; see for instance the van Eemeren, Grootendorst reference below. In this approach, an argument is regarded as an interactive protocol between individuals which attempts to resolve a disputed proposition. The protocol is regulated by certain rules of interaction and violations of these rules are fallacies. Many of the fallacies in the list below are best understood as being fallacies in this sense.
Examples of fallacious arguments
In the strictest sense, a logical fallacy is the incorrect application of a valid logical principle or an application of an nonexistent principle:
- Some acts of killing human beings are legal in this state.
- Some acts of killing human beings are illegal in this state.
- Therefore some acts of killing human beings are both legal and illegal in this state.
This is fallacious. Indeed, there is no logical principle which states
- For some x, P(x).
- For some y, Q(y).
- Then for some z, P(z) and Q(z).
The easiest way to show the above inference is invalid is by using Venn diagrams. In logical parlance, the inference is invalid, since under at least one interpretation of the predicates it is not validity preserving.
Unfortunately, few fallacious arguments are as clear cut as the above example suggests. A great many arguments involve causality, which is certainly not part of formal logic. Others involve psychological ploys such as use of power relationships between proposer and interlocutor, appeals to patriotism and morality, appeals to ego etc., to establish necessary intermediate (explicit or implicit) premises for an argument. Indeed, fallacies very often lay in unstated assumptions or implied premises in arguments that are not always obvious at first glance. One way to obscure a premise is through enthymeme.
We now give a few examples illustrating common errors in reasoning. Note that providing a critique of an argument has no relation to the validity of the conclusion. The conclusion could very well be valid, while the argument itself is unsound. See argument from fallacy.
In the following, we view an argument as a dialogue between a proposer and an interlocutor.
Example 1
James argues:
- Application of the death penalty is killing a human being.
- Killing a human being is wrong.
- Therefore, application of the death penalty is wrong.
This argument claims to prove the death penalty is wrong. This particular argument has the form of a categorical syllogism. Any argument must have premises as well as a conclusion. In this case we need to ask what the premises are, that is the set of assumptions the proposer of the argument can expect the interlocutor to grant. The first assumption is almost true by definition: the death penalty is the killing of a criminal who has been duly convicted under a process of law. The second assumption is less clear as to its meaning. Since the assertion has no quantifiers of any kind, it could mean any one of the following:
- Every act of killing a human being is wrong.
- Most acts of killing a human being are wrong.
- All acts of killing a human being are wrong, except those that are carried out for some legitimate purpose such as deterring serious crime.
- Some acts of killing a human being are wrong.
The third interpretation for example would be those of individuals who accept the Fifth Commandment under a common interpretation in Judeo-Christian theology. In that interpretation, the above syllogism would then fail to have validated its second premise. James may try to assume that his interlocutor believes every act of killing is wrong; if the interlocutor grants this then the argument is valid. In this case, the interlocutor is essentially conceding the point to James. However, the interlocutor is more likely to believe some acts of killing are not wrong, for instance those carried out in self defense or in legitimate warfare; and in this case James is not much better off than he was before he formulated the argument, since he now has to prove the assertion that the death penalty is not a legimate form of killing, which is a disguised form the original thesis. From the point of view the interlocutor, James commits the logical fallacy of begging the question.
Example 2
Barbara argues:
- Andre is a good tennis player.
- Therefore, Andre is 'good', that is to say a morally good person.
Here the problem is that the word good has different meanings, which is to say that it is an ambiguous word. In the premise, Barbara says that Andre is good at some particular activity, in this case tennis. In the conclusion, she says that Andre is a morally good person. These are clearly two different senses of the word "good". The premise might be true but the conclusion can still be false: Andre might be the best tennis player in the world but a rotten person morally. Appropriately, since it plays on an ambiguity, this sort of fallacy is called the fallacy of equivocation, that is, equating two incompatible terms or claims.
Example 3
A humorous variant of the fallacy of ambiguity is as follows. Ramesh argues:
- Nothing is better than eternal happiness.
- Eating a hamburger is better than nothing.
- Therefore, eating a hamburger is better than eternal happiness.
This argument has the appearance of an inference which applies transitivity of the two-placed relation is better than, which in this critique we grant is a valid property. The argument is an example of syntactic ambiguity. In fact, the first premise semantically does not predicate an attribute of the subject, as would for instance the assertion
- A potato is better than eternal happiness.
In fact it is semantically equivalent to the following universal quantification:
- Everything fails to be better than eternal happiness.
So instantiating this fact with eating a hamburger, it logically follows that
- Eating a hamburger fails to be better than eternal happiness.
Note that the premise A hamburger is better than nothing does not provide anything to this argument. This fact really means something such as
- Eating a hamburger is better than eating nothing at all.
Fallacies in the media and politics
Fallacies are used frequently by pundits in the media and politics. When one politician says to another, "You don't have the moral authority to say X", this could be an example of the argumentum ad hominem or personal attack fallacy; that is, attempting to disprove X, not by addressing validity of X but by attacking the person who asserted X. Arguably, the politician is not even attempting to make an argument against X, but is instead offering a moral rebuke against the interlocutor. For instance, if X is the assertion:
- The military uniform is a symbol of national strength and honor.
Then ostensibly, the politician is not trying to prove the contrary assertion. If this is the case, then there is no logically fallacious argument, but merely a personal opinion about moral worth. Thus identifying logical fallacies may be difficult and dependent upon context.
In the opposite direction is the fallacy of argument from authority. A classic example is the Ipse dixit—"He himself said it" argument—used throughout the Middle Ages in reference to Aristotle. A modern instance is "celebrity spokespersons" in advertisements: a product is good and you should buy/use/support it because your favorite celebrity endorses it.
An appeal to authority is always a logical fallacy though it can be an appropriate form of rational argument if, for example, it is an appeal to expert testimony. In this case, the expert witness must be recognized as such and all parties must agree that the testimony is appropriate to the circumstances. This form of argument is common in legal situations.
By definition, arguments with logical fallacies are invalid, but they can often be (re)written in such a way that they fit a valid argument form. The challenge to the interlocutor is, of course, to discover the false premise, that is the premise which makes the argument unsound.
A list of fallacies
Please note that this list is not exhaustive.
- Ad hominem (also called argumentum ad hominem or personal attack) Including:
- ad hominem abusive (also called argumentum ad personam)
- ad hominem circumstantial (also called ad hominem circumstantiae)
- ad hominem tu quoque (also called you too argument)
- Amphibology (also called amphiboly)
- Appeal to authority (also called argumentum ad verecundiam or argument by authority)
- Appeal to belief
- Appeal to consequences (also called argumentum ad consequentiae)
- Appeal to emotion including:
- Appeal to fear (also called argumentum ad metum or argumentum in terrorem)
- Appeal to flattery
- Appeal to the majority (also called argumentum ad populum)
- Appeal to pity (also called argumentum ad misericordiam)
- Appeal to ridicule
- Appeal to spite (also called argumentum ad odium)
- Two wrongs make a right
- Wishful thinking
- Appeal to motive
- Appeal to novelty (also called argumentum ad novitatem)
- Appeal to probability
- Appeal to tradition (also called argumentum ad antiquitatem or appeal to common practice)
- Argument from fallacy
- Argument from ignorance (also called argumentum ad ignorantiam or argument by lack of imagination)
- Argument from silence (also called argumentum ex silentio)
- Argumentum ad baculum (also called appeal to force)
- Argumentum ad crumenam (also called appeal to wealth)
- Argumentum ad lazarum (also called appeal to poverty)
- Argumentum ad nauseam (also called argument from repetition)
- Base rate fallacy
- Bandwagon fallacy (also called appeal to popularity, appeal to the people, or argumentum ad populum)
- Begging the question (also called petitio principii, circular argument or circular reasoning)
- Conjunction fallacy
- Correlative based fallacies including:
- Fallacy of many questions (also called complex question, loaded question or plurium interrogationum)
- False dilemma (also called false dichotomy or bifurcation)
- Denying the correlative
- Suppressed correlative
- Dicto simpliciter, including:
- Accident (also called a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid)
- Converse accident (also called a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter)
- Equivocation
- False analogy
- Fallacies of distribution:
- Faulty generalization including:
- Biased sample
- Hasty generalization (also called fallacy of insufficient statistics, fallacy of insufficient sample, fallacy of the lonely fact, leaping to a conclusion, hasty induction, secundum quid)
- Overwhelming exception
- Statistical special pleading
- Gambler's fallacy/Inverse gambler's fallacy
- Genetic fallacy
- Guilt by association / Honor by association
- Historian's fallacy
- Homunculus fallacy
- Ignoratio elenchi (also called irrelevant conclusion)
- Inappropriate interpretations or applications of statistics including:
- Invalid proof
- Lump of labour fallacy
- Meaningless statement
- Middle ground (also called argumentum ad temperantiam)
- Misleading vividness
- Naturalistic fallacy
- Negative proof
- Non sequitur including:
- No true Scotsman
- Package deal fallacy
- Pathetic fallacy
- Perfect solution fallacy
- Poisoning the well
- Questionable cause including:
- Correlation implies causation (also called cum hoc ergo propter hoc)
- Fallacy of the single cause
- Joint effect
- Post hoc (also called post hoc ergo propter hoc)
- Regression fallacy
- Texas sharpshooter fallacy
- Wrong direction
- Red herring
- Reification (also called hypostatization)
- Relativist fallacy (also called subjectivist fallacy)
- Shifting the Burden of proof
- Slippery slope
- Special pleading
- Straw man
- Style over substance fallacy
- Syllogistic fallacies, including:
See also
- Anecdotal evidence
- Cogency
- Cognitive bias
- College logic
- Critical thinking
- Demagogy
- Fallacies of definition
- Good argument
- Informal logic
- Invalid proof
- Sophism
- Soundness
- Spurious relationship
- Validity
References
- Aristoteles, On Sophistical Refutations, De Sophistici Elenchi.
- William of Ockham, Summa of Logic (ca. 1323) Part III.4.
- John Buridan, Summulae de dialectica Book VII.
- Francis Bacon, the doctrine of the idols in Novum Organum Scientiarum, Aphorisms concerning The Interpretation of Nature and the Kingdom of Man, XXIIIff.
- The Art of Controversy by Arthur Schopenhauer
- John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic - Raciocinative and Inductive. Book 5, Chapter 7, Fallacies of Confusion.
- C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies. Methuen London, 1970.
- D. H. Fischer, Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought, Harper Torchbooks, 1970.
- Douglas N. Walton, Informal logic: A handbook for critical argumentation. Cambridge University Press, 1989.
- F. H. van Eemeren and R. Grootendorst, Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies: A Pragma-Dialectical Perspective, Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates, 1992.
External links
- The Fallacy Files by Gary N. Curtis
- Logical Fallacies Online edition of Madsen Pirie's Book of the Fallacy
- Logic & Fallacies, from Atheism Web (no strict relation to Atheism)
- Logic and fallacies: How to spot a problem argument
- Stephen's Guide to the Logical Fallacies (Mirror)
- Bruce Thompson's table of fallacies
- Logical fallacies on WikiWikiWeb
- The Woolly-Thinker's Guide to Rhetoric
- The Autonomist's Logical Fallacies
- A list of Fallacious Arguments
- Propaganda techniques - Disinfopedia
- Informal Fallacies by Michael Connelly, contributed to the Critical Thinking Across the Curriculum Project.
- Papers on fallacies and argumentation by Douglas N. Walton.
- A Guide to Logical Fallacies, aimed at beginners - Paul Newall (2004)